Sydney, April - August 2019
Advisory Board | |
---|---|
Richard Garner My Supervisor, Senior Lecturer |
Steve Lack Director, Associate Professor |
Ross Street Founding Director, Emeritus Professor |
Dominic Verity Associate Director, Professor |
Tom Leinster calls them "ninja category theorists"
« One of my early Honours students at Macquarie University baffled his proposed Queensland graduate studies supervisor who asked whether the student knew the definition of a topological space. The aspiring researcher on dynamical systems answered positively:
"Yes, it is a relational $β$-module!"
I received quite a bit of flak from colleagues concerning that one; but the student Peter Kloeden went on to become a full professor of mathematics in Australia then Germany. »
— Ross Street (An Australian conspectus of higher categories)
Shown to be a linear exponential monad Garner's 2018 "Hypernormalisation" article.
In what follows: $M ≝ [0, 1] ⊆ ℝ$ and $\;\ovee ≝ +$
Garner: Linear exponential monads are the perfect setting for hypernormalisation.
which is related to... | and leads to... | |
---|---|---|
$[0,1]$ is an effect monoid | quantum mechanics foundations | $\D {[0, 1]}$ being a monad |
$(0,1)$ is a tricocycloid | quantum algebra | $\D {[0, 1]}$ being $\underbrace{\text{linear exponential}}_{\llap{\text{related to linear logic} \, ⟶ \, \textbf{quantum }\text{logic}}}$ |
$\Kl(\D {[0, 1]})$ is an effectus | quantum logic/computation | $\EM(\D {[0, 1]}) ≅ \Conv {[0, 1]}$ in a state-and-effect triangle |
⟹ How do these three notions relate?
If $𝒞$ has coproducts $+$, so does $\Kl(T)$
$x_1, …, x_n ∈ M$ orthogonal: if their partial sum is defined. When $\; x, y ∈ M \text{ orthogonal}$: $x \,⊥\, y$.
« Dr. Von Neumann, I would like to know what is a Hilbert space? » — David Hilbert (at the end of a lecture given by Von Neumann in Göttingen in 1929)
Also generalise
⟹ Can be thought of as generalising both propositions and probabilities
Can we generalise from $\D {[0,1]}$ to a general $\D M$, where $M$ is an arbitrary effect monoid?
⟶ If so, do we still have a linear exponential monad?
Lifts a certain tensor product $\star_{(0,1)}$ making $(\Set, \star_{(0,1)})$ symmetric monoidal to a coproduct in $\EM(\D M)$
One of the 3 ingredients to have a
⟶ Linear logic: argued to be the "proper incarnation" of quantum logic (see Pratt's 1992 article)
« One of the wild hopes that this suggests is the possibility of a direct connection with quantum mechanics… but let’s not dream too much! » — Girard (Linear logic, 1987)
What makes the tensor $A \star_{(0,1)} B ≝ A + (0,1) × A × B + B$ endow $\Set$ with a symmetric monoidal structure ⟶ the fact that $(0,1)$ is a tricocycloid in $\Set$
is an object $H ∈ 𝒞$ with an isomorphism $v:H ⊗ H → H ⊗ H$
satisfying the 3-cocycle condition:
A tricocycloid with a symmetry: symmetric tricocycloid.
Quantum algebraic objects introduced by Street in 1998
3-cocycle condition: $(v ⊗ 1)(1 ⊗ σ)(v ⊗ 1) = (1 ⊗ v) (v ⊗ 1)(1 ⊗ v)$
Why such a cocycle condition? How is it related to the problem at hand?
Cocycles in non-abelian cohomology ⟷ coherence conditions in higher-dimensional categories (associativity for 3-cocycle).
Here: associativity/coherence condition: an axiom of abstract convex sets (objects of the category of algebras)
Yang-Baxter equations: recurrent in quantum mechanics
Key lemma (Street and Garner): If $H ∈ 𝒞$ is a symmetric tricocycloid and $𝒞$ has finite coproducts $+$ over which $⊗$ distributes: we can co-universally make $(𝒞, ⋆_{H})$ a monoidal category (with $0$ as unit) by putting
$$A ⋆_{H} B ≝ A + H ⊗ A ⊗ B + B$$
$v ≝ \begin{cases} (0,1)^2 &→ (0,1)^2\\ (r,s) &↦ \Big(rs, \frac {rs^\ast}{(rs)^\ast}\Big) \end{cases}$
$γ ≝ (-)^\ast = \begin{cases} (0,1) &→ (0,1)\\ r &↦ r^\ast ≝ 1-r \end{cases}$
Very ad hoc to $\D {[0,1]}$. What about other probability monads? ⟶ Way harder to generalise
but... $\Kl(\D {[0,1]})$ (and the Kleisli category other probability monads as well) happens to be an effectus! (Jacobs 2018)
Examples of effectuses:
An effectus $𝔹$ induces a state-and-effect triangle:
$\Kl(\D \M)$ is an effectus (Zapata 2019): how is it related to $𝔹$?
If $𝔹$ has finite coproducts of $1$ as objects, with $q = [q^1, …, q^m]:m → n$:
from which we get
and $\Stat \text{ is fully-faithful } ⟺ \Nerve i \text{ is fully-faithful } ⟺ i \text{ is dense}$
When $M$ has normalisation:
Models of LL: does $\D M$ live in a model of linear logic?
$(\Set, ⋆_{\mathring M})$ is a SMC, but $0$ is a unit for $⋆_{\mathring M}$ ⟹ can't be closed.
Do we have a model of $\text{MELL}^{-}$ (without units)? (for Girard's proof nets)
Houston 2013: defines a good notion of model of $\text{MLL}^{-}$. Criterion: every arrow $A → B$ stems from a unique linear element of $A ⊸ B$ (ie a $γ_X:X → (A ⊸ B) ⊗ X$ such that $α_{A ⊸ B, X, Y} (γ_X ⊗ Y) = γ_{X ⊗ Y}:X ⊗ Y → (A ⊸ B) ⊗ (X ⊗ Y)$).
BUT condition not met in our case.
To fix $0$ being the unit for the tensor: how about $⋆_M$, where $M$ is seen as a lax tricocycloid? ⟶ Fails: Street's construction only yields a lax semi-monoidal category.
If $F:\catA → \catB$ is lax monoidal ⟹ the left Kan extension $\Lan F:\Psh\catA → \Psh\catB$ can be shown to be lax monoidal. So if $T:\catA → \catB$ is an opmonoidal monad, $\opposite T: \opposite\catA → \opposite\catB$ is lax monoidal, and $\Lan F:[\catA, \Set] → [\catB, \Set]$ is lax monoidal, thus $\opposite{\Lan F}:\opposite{[\catA, \Set]} → \opposite{[\catB, \Set]}$ is oplax monoidal. If $T$ is linear exponential, does $\opposite{\Lan F}$ remain linear exponential?